Wiener - Quentin Skinner´s Hobbes

download Wiener - Quentin Skinner´s Hobbes

of 11

Transcript of Wiener - Quentin Skinner´s Hobbes

  • 8/11/2019 Wiener - Quentin Skinners Hobbes

    1/11

    Sage Publications, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Political Theory.

    http://www.jstor.org

    Quentin Skinner's HobbesAuthor(s): Jonathan M. Wiener

    Source: Political Theory, Vol. 2, No. 3 (Aug., 1974), pp. 251-260Published by: Sage Publications, Inc.Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/190779Accessed: 13-08-2014 23:34 UTC

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available athttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of contentin a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.

    For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    This content downloaded from 146.155.94.33 on Wed, 13 Aug 2014 23:34:08 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=sagehttp://www.jstor.org/stable/190779http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/190779http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=sagehttp://www.jstor.org/
  • 8/11/2019 Wiener - Quentin Skinners Hobbes

    2/11

    POLITICAL

    THOUGHT

    AND

    POLITICAL

    ACTION:

    A

    Symposium

    on Quentin Skinner

    1. QUENTIN SKINNER'S HOBBES

    JONATHAN M.

    WIENER

    University of California (Irvine)

    OR

    A

    LONG

    TIME

    it

    has

    seemed to

    many

    that

    Hobbes

    must

    be

    understood in

    the

    context

    of

    social and

    political change

    m

    seventeenth-

    century

    England,

    particularly

    in relation to the Civil War, which so

    frightened

    and

    preoccupied

    him.

    Aubrey

    wrote that

    Hobbes's interest

    in

    politics

    and the

    war

    was

    so

    great

    that

    "for ten

    years

    altogether

    his

    thoughts

    were

    much,

    or

    almost

    altogether,

    unhinged

    from the mathemat-

    ics,"

    and Hobbes

    himself

    wrote,

    "if

    in time as in

    place,

    there

    were

    degrees

    of

    high

    and

    low,

    I

    verily

    believe the

    highest

    of

    time would be that which

    passed

    betwixt

    1640

    and

    1660."'

    While

    many

    have considered the

    links between Hobbes's

    thought

    and

    his

    time,

    a recent

    senes

    of articles

    by

    Quentin

    Skinner

    has made an

    important

    contribution

    to the

    argument.

    Sklnner has

    placed

    Hobbes's

    political

    thought

    in the context

    of

    mid-seventeenth-century English

    political

    and intellectual

    history,

    arguing

    that

    those

    who have

    not

    done

    so-particularly

    Warrender-have

    come to

    "historically

    absurd"

    nterpreta-

    tions

    of the

    texts,

    and that those who

    previously

    made

    the

    effort

    have

    seriously

    exaggerated

    he

    extent of

    Hobbes's

    solation

    from his

    contempo-

    raries.

    EDITORS' NOTE. This Symposium was organized by Professor Benamin Barber, at

    the time our

    Modern

    Political

    Theory

    Editor,

    now

    an

    editor

    Political

    Theory,

    Vol. 2 No.

    3,

    August

    1974,

    ?

    1974

    Sage

    Publications,

    Inc.

    [2511

    This content downloaded from 146.155.94.33 on Wed, 13 Aug 2014 23:34:08 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Wiener - Quentin Skinners Hobbes

    3/11

    [2521

    POLITICAL

    THEORY

    / AUGUST 1974

    Skinner'smost

    recent

    article

    begins

    with

    the

    political

    situation

    m

    1649

    The

    king

    had been

    executed,

    the House of

    Lords

    abolished,

    and

    Cromwell

    declaredhead of the new Commonwealth;he newgovernment's irst task

    was to

    persuade

    moderate

    and hostile

    groups

    that

    the

    revolution

    was

    really

    over.

    That

    is,

    Cromwell

    needed

    a

    theory

    of

    political

    obligation

    which

    could

    persuade

    Presbyterians

    and

    Royalists

    to

    abandon

    their

    sworn

    obligations

    to

    protect

    the life

    of the

    king,

    take

    the

    oath of

    allegiance

    to

    the

    Commonwealth,

    and

    obey

    what

    they

    considered to

    be

    a

    usurping

    power.

    Such

    a

    theory

    was formulated

    by

    a

    group

    of

    moderate

    intellectuals,

    first

    uncovered

    by Zagornn

    nd often called the

    "Engagers",

    n their

    own

    day,

    many

    were considered

    "Hobblsts,"

    but their

    relations with

    Hobbes

    were

    virtually

    unknown

    until Skinner's

    studies.2

    For

    Skinner,

    this

    group

    "provides

    the

    context

    within

    which the main

    alms

    and

    severalof

    the most

    characteristic doctrines

    of Hobbes's

    political

    philosophy

    can best be

    understood."3

    The earliest

    form of

    their

    argument

    was that

    the

    Pauline

    njunction

    to

    obey

    the

    powers

    that be

    as ordained

    by

    God

    was

    valid

    even

    for

    usurping

    powers.

    But

    Royalists

    and

    Presbyterians

    could

    argue

    on

    good

    scriptural

    authoritythat God neverordainsbut often permitsthe wickedto rule,and

    that the

    Apostle

    does

    not

    require

    hat

    tyranny

    not be resisted.

    The

    politically

    necessary

    reply

    to this

    argument

    was

    formulated

    first

    by

    Anthony

    Ascham,

    not

    by

    Hobbes. Ascham wrote in

    1649,

    shortly

    before

    Leviathanwas

    published,

    that men

    were

    obligated

    to

    obey

    whatever

    power

    existed,

    simply

    because

    it was

    protecting

    them from each

    other,

    which

    was

    its

    essential

    duty,

    and

    that

    the alternativewas a war

    of

    all

    against

    all. This

    argument

    was

    then

    taken

    up

    by

    MarchamontNedham and

    a series of

    intellectuals Skinner

    identifies

    and

    discusses,

    all of whom

    managed

    to

    "avoidquestions about providenceby focusing instead on the questionof

    what

    political

    society

    is

    for,

    and

    answenng

    that

    it

    is

    essentially

    a

    product

    of

    necessity

    and a

    means

    to secure

    peace

    and

    protection,"

    and

    that such

    protection required

    absolute

    power.4

    But while these

    "de

    facto"

    theonsts

    as Skinner calls

    them,

    made

    their

    new

    theory

    of

    obligation

    explicit,

    "none of them

    argued

    for

    it

    in

    a

    very

    systematic

    way,

    and

    few of

    them

    ever

    stated,

    except

    in

    a

    very fragmentary

    manner,

    the

    pessirmstic

    view

    of

    man's

    political

    nature

    upon

    which the

    theory

    depended."

    Only

    one,

    in

    fact,

    managed

    to

    "elirmnate

    all

    invoca-

    tions of God's

    providence,

    and to

    predicate

    a de facto theory of

    political

    obligation

    entirely

    on an account

    of

    the

    political

    nature

    of

    man."5 That

    man

    was

    Thomas

    Hobbes.

    This content downloaded from 146.155.94.33 on Wed, 13 Aug 2014 23:34:08 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Wiener - Quentin Skinners Hobbes

    4/11

    Wiener

    /

    SYMPOSIUM

    [2531

    Between

    February

    1650 and the

    middle

    of

    1651,

    five of Hobbes's

    political

    works

    were

    published,

    the

    last of which was

    Levauthan.

    According

    to Shknner,"they were immediatelyrecognizedby the other lay defenders

    of

    de

    facto

    powers

    as

    giving

    the most authoritative

    presentation

    of

    a

    view

    of

    political

    obligation

    at which

    they

    had all

    independently

    arnved."

    Hobbes,

    in

    Skinner's

    view,

    "endorses

    all

    the most

    characterstic

    claims of

    the

    de

    facto

    theorists",

    his doctrines

    represent

    "a somewhat belated

    though highly important

    contribution to

    the

    lay

    defense of

    'engage-

    ment.'

    "6 And it was Hobbes's

    explicit

    intention to

    provide

    such

    a

    defense,

    Slknner

    wntes,

    pointing

    to

    Hobbes's

    proud

    claim in

    1656

    that the

    Levtathan

    "framed

    the

    minds

    of a thousand

    gentlemen

    to a conscientious

    obedience to

    present

    government,

    which otherwise

    would

    have

    wavered

    on

    that

    point,"

    and

    to the

    conclusion

    of

    Leviathan,

    where Hobbes wrote that

    his book

    was

    motivated

    by

    the

    discovery

    that "the civil warshave

    not

    yet

    sufficiently

    taught

    men

    in

    what

    point

    of time it is

    that a

    subject

    becomes

    obliged

    to

    the

    conqueror;

    nor what is

    conquest;

    nor how it

    comes

    about,

    that

    it

    obliges

    men to

    obey

    its laws."7

    "There is

    nothing

    unusual or even

    particularly

    onginal

    about Hobbes's

    most characteristic

    political

    beliefs,"

    Skinner

    concludes.

    Yet

    the

    'Hobblsts'

    of the 1650s were second- and third-ratethinkers, the ideological troops

    who

    forged

    the

    intellectual

    weapons

    for

    Cromwell's

    cause,

    whose own

    work

    is

    distinctly

    unmemorable.

    Does Skiner

    mean

    to reduce

    Hobbes to

    their level? On

    the

    contrary;

    Skinner's

    conclusion is that Hobbes's

    "special

    status

    as a

    political

    writer" is a

    consequence

    of

    his

    method,

    "the reasons

    he

    gave

    for

    holding

    his

    political

    beliefs,

    rather than in the

    beliefs

    themselves."8

    The

    question

    then becomes

    whether

    Skinner's

    historical

    perspective

    on

    Hobbes

    changes

    our

    reading

    of his

    political thought,

    or whether it

    provides

    simply "another dimension," one of interest to political and intellectual

    historians,

    but not

    necessarily

    to

    political

    theorists and

    philosophers.

    Skinner

    takes

    his

    analysis

    to

    indicate that

    the

    interpretation

    offered

    by

    Taylor,

    Warrender,

    and F

    C.

    Hood,

    who

    depend

    exclusively

    on

    a close

    reading

    of the

    texts

    to

    argue

    that

    Hobbes saw

    the

    laws

    of

    nature

    as

    commands of

    God,

    can

    be

    shown to

    be

    "historcally

    absurd."9 The

    understanding

    of

    texts,

    Skinner

    writes,

    "presupposes

    the

    grasp

    both

    of

    what

    they

    were intended to

    mean,

    and how

    this

    meaning

    was

    intended

    to

    be

    taken."

    The social

    context

    provides

    "an

    ultimate

    framework"for this

    "recovery of

    intentions."'0

    If Warrender's

    nterpretation

    of Hobbes is

    correct,

    then

    "every

    contemporary-every

    follower,

    every

    opponent,

    every

    sympathizer-all equally

    missed

    the

    point

    of

    his

    theory

    All of

    them,

    This content downloaded from 146.155.94.33 on Wed, 13 Aug 2014 23:34:08 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Wiener - Quentin Skinners Hobbes

    5/11

    (254]

    POLITICAL

    THEORY

    / AUGUST

    1974

    moreover

    (surely

    an

    astounding

    coincidence),

    were

    mistaken n

    exactly

    the

    same

    way,"

    since

    every

    single

    contemporary

    cited

    Hobbes

    as

    having

    "located the groundsof political obligation in the paramountneed for

    protection,"

    tself a

    consequence

    of

    man's

    nasty

    and brutish

    nature.

    1

    If

    Warrender's

    nterpretation

    s

    correct,

    Hobbeshimself

    must

    be

    seen

    as

    having

    presented

    "a

    traditional

    type

    of

    natural

    aw

    theory

    in

    a

    mannerso

    convoluted that

    it

    was

    everywhere

    taken for

    the

    work

    of

    a

    complete

    utilitarian,"

    yet

    Hobbes "failed

    altogether

    either

    to

    disown

    the

    alarmungly

    radicalwriterswho

    cited

    hLs

    uthority,

    or

    to disarm

    his

    innumerable

    ritics

    by

    pointing

    out their

    misconceptions

    of

    his

    intentions."

    To

    prove

    this

    point,

    Skinner has

    published

    a

    previously

    unknown

    manuscript

    of

    Hobbes's,

    his

    only

    known

    reply

    to a

    critic,

    in which he reiteratesthe

    preeminentplace

    of self-interest

    n

    his

    theory

    of

    obligation.i

    2

    Skinner's

    work thus constitutes

    a

    most

    impressive

    demonstration

    of the

    argument

    hat

    "the

    question

    of

    what Hobbes's

    theory

    is" is neither

    "prior

    to"

    nor

    separate

    from

    the

    question

    of its historical

    location;

    Warrender's

    demand

    for

    an

    exclusive

    adherenceto

    the text should

    be

    rejected

    because

    it

    has

    led

    to

    "historically

    absurd" conclusions

    about the intentions

    of

    everyone

    present,

    including

    Hobbes;

    we

    need

    "less

    philosophy,

    and

    more

    history"

    n

    the

    study

    of

    Hobbes.1

    From this

    perspective,

    MacPherson's

    work

    on

    Hobbes

    is

    plausible

    but

    incomplete.

    His

    method

    for

    uncovering

    the

    assumptions

    governing

    Hobbes's

    thinking

    is the same

    as Warrender's:

    closer

    reading

    of

    the

    text.

    But,

    Skinner

    argues,

    if

    MacPherson

    is

    to

    prove

    that certain

    social

    conditions influenced

    and

    limited Hobbes's

    assumptions

    about

    man,

    he

    must

    go

    outside

    the

    text and

    provide

    historical

    evidence

    that

    a

    "possessive

    market"

    society

    actually

    existed m

    Hobbes's

    day

    and thereforecould

    have

    determined

    Hobbes's

    assumptions.1

    Skinnersees S. I. Mintz'sHuntingof Leviathanas the most important

    recent

    interpretive

    work

    because

    it

    goes

    outside

    Hobbes's

    text to

    locate

    him

    "within

    contemporary

    ethical

    debate."

    The

    problem

    with Mintz

    is

    that

    he

    is

    simply

    wrong

    in

    supporting

    the

    conventional

    interpretation

    of

    Hobbes

    as

    having

    been

    important

    m

    his

    time

    only

    for the "intense

    opposition"

    he

    provoked.

    His

    influence,

    Skinner

    shows

    conclusively,

    was

    not

    entirely

    negative,

    and he was

    not

    an isolated

    figure.

    Here

    Skinner

    presents

    some

    fascinating

    vidence

    that

    Hobbes

    was

    widely

    read in

    his

    day,

    apparently

    a best-seller.

    Skinner

    cites a

    catalogue

    of "the most

    vendible

    books in England" or 1658 which lists Hobbesas the thirdbiggest-selling

    writer,

    surpassed

    only

    by

    Bacon

    and

    Raleigh.

    Samuel

    Pepys

    as

    late

    as

    1668

    found Leviathan

    "so

    mightily

    called

    for"

    that

    he

    had to

    spend

    three

    times

    This content downloaded from 146.155.94.33 on Wed, 13 Aug 2014 23:34:08 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Wiener - Quentin Skinners Hobbes

    6/11

    Wiener

    /

    SYMPOSIUM

    [2551

    the

    original

    price

    to

    get

    a

    copy,

    even

    though

    two additional editions had

    been

    published

    that

    year.

    Hobbes was

    widely enough

    known so that the

    "Hobbist"becamea familiar

    figure

    on the Restoration

    stage.

    6

    But

    Mintz's

    problem

    is not

    just

    his

    conclusions;

    his method too

    is

    faulty

    Skinner

    observes

    that Mintz's concern is

    exclusively

    for

    the

    reactions

    of

    other intellectuals

    to

    Hobbes,

    rather

    than

    his

    relations

    with

    them;

    Mintz fails to

    "include some account of

    political theory

    as a social

    activity

    "'

    7

    But

    it

    is at

    precisely

    this

    point

    that

    Skinner's own

    analysis

    is least

    complete.

    His

    conception

    of

    "political

    theory

    as a social

    activity"

    is

    restricted

    too

    narrowly

    to the

    political positions

    of

    the

    intellectuals

    on

    the

    issues

    of the

    early

    1650s,

    without

    considering

    their

    location in the

    larger

    society,

    their own

    experience

    of social

    change

    and

    political

    unrest,

    and

    their

    relations to

    particular

    social

    classes and

    political

    groups.

    Skinner

    shows

    convincingly

    that Hobbes is

    part

    of a

    group

    of

    ideologists,

    but he

    never

    says

    precisely

    whose

    ideology

    it is-whether

    their

    particular

    defense

    of the Commonwealth

    was

    based

    on the

    world

    view of a small

    circle

    of

    rootless

    intellectuals,

    unrelated to

    any

    of

    the

    significant

    social

    and

    political

    forces

    of the

    time,

    or whether

    they represented

    particulargroups.

    A study dealing with these questionswould requirea knowledgeof the

    political sociology

    of

    seventeenth-century

    England;

    uch

    a

    study

    is

    possible

    now

    more

    than

    ever

    before.

    We

    now

    possess

    a

    substantial

    body

    of

    secondary

    literature

    on the

    relationship

    among

    politics,

    social

    structure,

    and social

    change

    m

    seventeenth-century

    England,

    more than

    we have on

    any

    other historical

    period.i

    8

    We not

    only

    have some

    of the

    necessary

    secondary

    sources;

    we

    also

    have some models for how the

    necessary

    ideological analysis

    could

    be

    carried out. If we are to take

    seriously

    Skinner's claim that Hobbes's

    theory was not the work of an isolated individual,but ratherthe mutual

    creation

    of a self-conscious

    group

    of

    intellectuals,

    then we

    should consider

    that

    group

    m the

    terms

    set

    by

    Lucien

    Goldmann's

    tudy

    of the

    Jansenists

    and Michael Walzer's

    work on

    the Puritan

    clergy;

    both

    writers

    deal with

    the

    ways

    small

    groups

    of

    self-conscious

    itellectuals

    create new world

    views

    out

    of

    particularexperiences

    of

    social

    change,

    which

    bnng

    them to

    distinctive

    political

    positions.'

    9

    Skinner's

    focus

    on

    Hobbes's

    intentions

    m

    publishing

    Leviathanm

    1651

    puts

    his

    political theory

    in too narrowa

    historicalcontext. Skinnershows

    convincingly what those intentions were; but Leviathan was not only a

    defense

    of

    the Commonwealth. The

    argument

    m it is

    remarkably

    lose

    to

    that

    of the Elements

    of

    Law

    and

    De

    Cive,

    which were

    written much

    This content downloaded from 146.155.94.33 on Wed, 13 Aug 2014 23:34:08 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Wiener - Quentin Skinners Hobbes

    7/11

    [256]

    POLITICAL

    THEORY

    /

    AUGUST 1974

    earlier,

    and

    published

    in

    1640

    and

    1642;

    Hobbes's

    political

    philosophy

    seems

    to

    have been worked

    out,

    not

    at

    all

    as a

    response

    o the

    engagement

    controversy,but much earlier, in the 1630s, and it seems to have been

    substantiallycomplete

    before

    he 'fled'

    England.

    Hobbes

    In

    the

    1630s could not have been

    intending

    to

    provide

    a

    philosophical

    defense of

    future

    regicides.

    Even

    in terms

    of

    Skinner's

    own

    rather narrow interest

    in

    "intentions,"

    it is

    necessary

    o look at Hobbes

    in

    a

    broaderhistorical

    context

    and to

    examine

    at

    least the

    political

    character

    of

    his

    philosophy

    in

    the 1630s. It

    was first

    of all

    absolutist,

    a defense

    of

    the recent moves

    toward

    absolutism

    by

    Elizabeth,James,

    and Charles-a

    theory

    of absolutism

    distinguishedby

    an

    absence of

    religious

    content;

    a

    theory

    perhaps

    informed

    by

    Hobbes's

    knowledge

    of

    continental

    absolut-

    ism,

    which

    he observed

    on his travels

    to France

    n

    the

    1630s.

    Skinner

    touches

    on some

    of these

    separate

    points,

    but never

    puts

    them

    together.

    He observes

    that the

    "need

    for

    absolute

    power"

    was

    the

    "most

    notable

    feature"

    of

    Hobbes's

    theory

    in

    its

    day;

    he uncovers

    impressive

    evidence

    in

    Hobbes's

    correspondence

    that uhs

    political

    ideas were

    "widely

    accepted"

    on

    the

    continent,

    particularly

    among

    French

    scientists,

    who

    "recognized

    and

    sympathized

    with his most

    ambitious

    hopes

    for

    a

    Science

    of Politics."20 Moreprecisely,

    it was Hobbes's

    science

    of absolutism

    that

    aroused

    the enthusiasm

    of French

    scientists;

    they

    seem to have

    recognized

    the

    intellectual

    importance

    of

    replacing

    the Divine

    Right

    justification

    of

    the

    French absolute

    state

    with a

    more

    modern

    and rational

    one.

    Further

    study

    of Hobbes's

    relations

    with French

    society

    and

    politics

    would

    illuminate

    this

    point.

    The

    view

    of Hobbes

    as

    having

    orginally

    developed

    his

    philosophy

    as

    a

    defense of

    absolutism,

    particularly

    hat of

    James

    and

    Charles,

    s

    not at

    all

    incompatible

    with

    Skinner's

    picture

    of

    Hobbes

    in

    1651

    arguing

    for

    Cromwell,as R S. Petershas suggested.He sees Hobbesas arguingthat,

    since

    Charles's

    move

    toward

    absolutism

    had

    been

    defeated,

    the

    next

    best

    thing

    for

    England

    was

    an

    absolute

    government

    headed

    by

    Cromwell-who

    "should

    become

    king by

    common

    consent

    and

    dispense

    with

    incompetent

    Parliamentarians."2

    If

    we are

    to

    have

    a full

    account

    of

    the creation

    of

    this science

    of

    absolutism

    "as

    a

    social

    activity,"

    we

    need

    to examine the

    relationship

    between

    Hobbes's

    own

    experience

    in

    society

    and his distinctive

    world

    view,

    to

    determine

    whether

    there

    is an

    identifiable

    social

    position

    from

    which he gaied his particularperspectiveon politicsandsociety Skinner

    does an

    outstanding

    ob

    on Hobbes's

    intellectual

    milieu

    in the

    1650s,

    but

    he

    does

    not

    consider

    Hobbes'srelations

    with

    society

    in the

    first

    fifty years

    This content downloaded from 146.155.94.33 on Wed, 13 Aug 2014 23:34:08 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Wiener - Quentin Skinners Hobbes

    8/11

    Wiener

    /

    SYMPOSIUM

    [2571

    of uhs

    ife,

    the

    penod

    before 1640 when he was

    developing

    his science

    of

    absolutism

    as a member of the household of the

    great

    aristocratic and

    royalist family of the Cavendishes.Hobbeshad been "one of the common

    people,"

    as he himself

    admitted,

    before

    entering

    the Cavendish

    household;

    in exile after

    1640,

    he tutored the future Charles

    II,

    and later the Earlof

    Clarendon

    wrote of Hobbes's close

    relationship

    with the

    "nobility, by

    whose

    bread

    he

    hath been

    always

    sustained."22

    Thus

    Hobbes's

    own social

    position,

    at least to the time he was

    fifty,

    was

    that

    of a

    common-bor

    intellectual

    who "made it"

    into the

    heart

    of

    aristocratic and

    royalist

    circles. He

    was

    as close as

    any

    commoner

    could be

    to

    the

    top

    of

    Englishsociety;

    this

    position

    must

    have

    played

    a

    significant

    role in

    the formation

    of

    his ideas about

    man's

    nasty

    and

    competitive

    nature,

    and about the

    resulting

    need

    for

    absolute

    power.

    A

    clearer

    conception

    of the

    relationship

    between social

    class

    and absolutism in this

    period

    would

    clarify

    Hobbes's

    position considerably

    23

    An

    alternative

    to

    viewing

    Hobbes

    primarily

    n

    terms of his

    relationship

    to the

    top

    of

    English society

    is to

    consider

    his

    own

    experience

    of

    social

    mobility

    in a time of

    rapid

    social

    change

    and

    widespread political

    unrest.

    Such

    an

    interpretation

    of Hobbes is

    suggested

    in Michael

    Walzer's

    Revolution of the Saints. Walzer suggests that Hobbes's science of

    absolutism

    can

    best be

    interpreted

    as an

    "ideology

    of transition"

    which

    "met

    the human

    needs that

    arise whenever

    traditional

    controls

    give way

    and

    hlerarcuhcal

    tatus and

    corporate

    privilege

    are called into

    question."

    Hobbes

    responded

    to

    social

    "unsettledness"

    by

    calling

    for an absolute

    central

    power,

    on

    the

    one

    hand,

    and a

    narrowing

    of

    people's

    energies

    rom

    political

    to

    economic

    competition,

    on the other.

    In this

    view,

    Hobbes

    was

    responding

    not so much to

    particular

    elements

    of

    the

    traditional

    order,

    such

    as the

    monarchy

    and its

    interests,

    as he was

    to

    the

    "disorder

    of the

    transition period." The old order was only a part, and not the most

    important

    part,

    of his

    experience;

    he

    lived

    most

    of

    his life amid the

    breakdown

    of

    that

    order and in

    exile from that

    breakdown. The

    advocacy

    of

    absolutism

    can

    be seen

    as one of the

    ways

    in

    which

    some men seek

    to

    cope

    with their

    experience

    of

    the breakdown

    of the

    old

    order;

    Puritan

    sainthood is

    another

    way

    24

    In

    Slknner's

    work

    on

    Hobbes,

    then,

    he has

    considered

    the

    methodolog-

    ical

    problem

    of

    the

    relationship

    of

    political thought

    to

    history

    and

    argued

    that

    political

    ideas cannot be

    understood

    apart

    from

    their historical

    context. His studies of Hobbes's

    relationship

    o the

    engagement

    controver-

    sy

    of the

    1650s

    can be

    considered

    a

    case

    study

    of the method

    he

    is

    advocating

    for

    the

    history

    of

    political

    theory

    as a

    whole.

    These

    studies,

    it

    This content downloaded from 146.155.94.33 on Wed, 13 Aug 2014 23:34:08 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Wiener - Quentin Skinners Hobbes

    9/11

    [258]

    POLITICAL

    THEORY /AUGUST

    1974

    seems to

    me,

    identify conclusively

    the

    contemporary

    political

    and

    intellectual context

    of Leviathan and

    demonstrate

    that

    an

    exclusive

    reliance on textual analysis eads to a faulty understanding, articularly f

    Hobbes's

    heory

    of

    obligation.

    Skinner

    has

    thus

    made

    an

    important

    contribution

    to

    the

    study

    of

    Hobbes.

    However,

    his

    conception

    of

    the "historical context"

    must

    be

    broadened-from

    a focus on the

    political

    intentions

    of the

    Hobbist

    intellectuals in relation to

    the

    Commonwealth,

    to

    a

    concern for

    the

    social

    origins

    of Hobbes's

    philosophy

    before

    the Civil

    War,

    and more

    generally

    o

    the relations between

    social

    change,

    the

    new

    science,

    and

    the

    politics

    of

    absolutism

    in

    the

    sixteenth

    and seventeenth

    centuries.

    This

    would

    appear

    to

    require

    a

    way

    of

    doing history

    ratherdifferent fromSkinner's-one tied

    less

    exclusively

    to the intellectual

    history

    of the

    1650s,

    one

    explicitly

    comparative,

    peculative,

    and theoretical.

    NOTES

    1.

    John

    Aubrey, Brief

    Lives,

    ed. A.

    Clark,

    2

    vols.

    (Oxford, 1898), I,

    333;

    The

    English

    Works

    of

    Thomas

    Hobbes,

    ed.

    W

    Molesworth,

    11

    vols.

    (London, 1839), VI,

    165.

    2. Perez

    Zagorn,

    A

    History of

    Political

    Thought

    in

    the

    English

    Revolution

    (London, 1954).

    3.

    Quentin

    Skinner,

    "Conquest

    and

    Consent:

    Thomas

    Hobbes

    and

    the

    Engage-

    ment

    Controversy,"

    in

    G.

    E.

    Aylmer

    (ed.),

    The

    Interregnum:

    The

    Quest

    for

    Settlement,

    1646-1660

    (London,

    1972),

    80.

    This

    group

    is

    also

    discussed

    by

    Skmner

    in

    "History

    and

    Ideology

    in

    the

    English

    Revolution,"

    Historical

    Journal

    8

    (1965),

    151-178,

    and

    "The

    Ideological

    Context

    of Hobbes's

    Political

    Thought,"

    Historical

    Journal

    9

    (1966),

    287-317;

    this article has

    been revised:

    "The

    Context

    of Hobbes's

    Theory

    of Political

    Obligation,"

    in

    Maurice Cranston

    and Richard S.

    Peters

    (eds.),

    Hobbes

    and Rousseau

    (Garden City,

    N.Y., 1972),

    109-142.

    4.

    "Conquest

    and

    Consent," 88,

    91.

    5.

    "Conquest

    and

    Consent,"

    94.

    6.

    "Conquest

    and

    Consent,"

    94, 95,

    96.

    7

    EW

    VII,

    335-336,

    Thomas

    Hobbes,

    Leviathan,

    ed.,

    C. B.

    MacPherson

    (Baltimore,

    1968),

    719.

    8.

    "Conquest

    and

    Consent,"

    97-98.

    9.

    "Context

    of Hobbes's

    Theory,"

    142;

    A.

    E.

    Taylor,

    "The

    Ethical Doctrine

    of

    Hobbes,"

    Philosophy

    103

    (1938),

    109;

    H.

    Warrender,

    The

    Political

    Philosophy

    of

    Hobbes

    (Oxford,

    1957);

    F C.

    Hood,

    The Devine

    Politics

    of

    Thomas

    Hobbes

    (Oxford,

    1964).

    Hood

    is

    important,

    Skinner

    writes,

    for

    making

    "only

    the most colorful

    and

    least plausible contribution to a type of study which is itself misconceived." Skinner,

    "Hobbes's

    Leviathan,"

    Historcal

    Journal

    7

    (1964),

    322.

    This content downloaded from 146.155.94.33 on Wed, 13 Aug 2014 23:34:08 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Wiener - Quentin Skinners Hobbes

    10/11

    Wiener

    /

    SYMPOSIUM

    [2591

    10.

    Quentin

    Skinner,

    "Meaning

    and

    Understanding

    m

    the

    History

    of

    Ideas,"

    History

    and

    Theory

    8

    (1969),

    48-49

    11. "Context of Hobbes's Theory," 137-138.

    12. "Context

    of Hobbes's

    Theory,"

    141,

    Skinner,

    "Hobbes on

    Sovereignty

    An

    Unknown

    Discussion,"

    Political Studies

    13

    (1965),

    213-218.

    13.

    "Hobbes's

    Levtathan,"

    333.

    14. C. B.

    MacPherson,

    The Political

    Theory

    of

    Possessive Individualism

    (Oxford,

    1964);

    "Hobbes's

    Leviathan,"

    323.

    15.

    Samuel

    1.

    Mintz,

    The

    Hunting

    of

    Leviathan

    (Cambridge,

    1962),

    155. This is

    the

    analysis

    of

    virtually

    all

    commentators until

    Skinner;

    for

    references

    see

    "Context

    of Hobbes's

    Theory,"

    109-110.

    16. "Context

    of Hobbes's

    Theory,"

    113,

    115-116.

    17

    "Hobbes's

    Leviathan,"

    333.

    18.

    The

    most

    important

    works include

    Lawrence

    Stone,

    Causes

    of

    the

    English

    Revolution,

    1529-1642

    (New

    York,

    1972),

    and

    Criss

    of

    the

    Aristocracy,

    1558-1641

    (Oxford,

    1965);

    R. H.

    Tawney,

    "The Rise of the

    Gentry,"

    Economic

    History

    Review

    11

    (1941),

    1-38;

    H.

    R.

    Trevor-Roper,

    "The General

    Crisis of

    the

    Seventeenth

    Century,"

    Past

    and Present

    16

    (1959), 31-64,

    Christopher

    Hill,

    Century of

    Revolution

    1603-1714

    (London,

    1961);

    Patrick

    Collinson,

    The

    Elizabethan Puritan

    Movement

    (Berkeley,

    1967);

    Robert

    Brenner,

    "The Civil

    War

    Politics

    of London's Merchant

    Community,"

    Past

    and Present

    58

    (February,

    1973).

    19.

    Luclen

    Goldmann,

    The Hidden

    God

    (New

    York,

    1964);

    Michael

    Walzer,

    Revolution

    of

    the

    Saints

    (Cambridge,

    1965).

    20. "Conquest and Consent," 92; Quentin Skiner, "Thomas Hobbes and His

    Disciples

    in

    France

    and

    England,"

    Comparative

    Studies in

    Society

    and

    History

    8

    (1965-66),

    164.

    For Hobbes's relations with

    English

    scientists,

    see

    Skinner,

    "Thomas

    Hobbes and

    the Nature

    of

    the

    Early

    Royal Society,"

    Historical Journal

    12

    (1969),

    217-239. Skinner

    does

    not

    place

    the

    seventeenth-century

    French

    scientists

    with

    whom Hobbes

    associated

    in their own

    political

    context;

    for

    instance,

    the

    patron

    of

    Mersenne's

    circle was

    Richelieu,

    who

    played

    a definitive role m the

    development

    of

    French

    absolutism. Hobbes's influence

    on

    subsequent

    continental

    absolutist

    theory

    has

    been

    noted

    by

    Skinner;

    "the

    apologists

    for absolutism

    in

    France

    accepted

    the

    relevance of Hobbes's doctrine."

    "Ideological

    Context,"

    289

    21. Richard

    S.

    Peters,

    Hobbes

    (London, 1967),

    35.

    22. Cited In

    Christopher

    Hill,

    The World Turned

    Upside

    Down

    (London, 1972),

    313. The Cavendish

    family

    is discussed

    frequently

    m

    Stone, Crisls

    of Aristocracy.

    23.

    The

    starting

    point

    for a consideration of

    social class

    in relation

    to

    absolutism

    is

    Barrington

    Moore, Jr.,

    Social

    Origins of

    Dictatorship

    and

    Democracy

    (Boston,

    1966),

    esp.

    chs.

    1,

    2,

    7

    24.

    Walzer,

    Revolution

    of

    Saints,

    312-313.

    Selected Works

    by

    Quentin

    Skinner

    "Conquest and Consent: Thomas Hobbes and the Engagement Controversy," in G. E.

    Aylmer

    (ed.),

    The

    Interregnum:

    The

    Quest

    for

    Settlement,

    1646-1660

    (London,

    1972).

    This content downloaded from 146.155.94.33 on Wed, 13 Aug 2014 23:34:08 UTCAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/11/2019 Wiener - Quentin Skinners Hobbes

    11/11

    [260]

    POLITICAL

    THEORY

    /

    AUGUST 1974

    "The Context

    of Hobbes's

    Theory

    of

    Political

    Obligation,"

    in

    Maurice

    Cranston

    and

    Richard

    S.

    Peters

    (eds.),

    Hobbes and

    Rousseau

    (Garden

    City,

    N.Y.,

    1972),

    109-142.

    "History

    and

    Ideology

    in

    the

    English

    Revolution,"

    Historical Journal

    8

    (1965),

    151-178.

    "Hobbes's

    Leviathan,"

    Historical

    Journal

    7

    (1964),

    321-333.

    "Hobbes

    on

    Soverelgnty

    An

    Unknown

    Discussion,"

    Political Studies

    13

    (1965),

    213-218.

    "The

    Ideological

    Context

    of

    Hobbes's Political

    Thought,"

    Historcal

    Journal 9

    (1966),

    286-317

    "The Limits of

    Historical

    Explanations,"

    Philosophy

    41

    (1966),

    199-215.

    "Meaning

    and

    Understanding

    in the

    History

    of

    Ideas,"

    History

    and

    Theory

    8

    (1969),

    3-53.

    "Thomas Hobbes

    and

    His

    Disciples

    in France and

    England," Comparative

    Studies

    in

    Society

    and

    History

    8

    (1965-66),

    153-167

    "Thomas

    Hobbes

    and the

    Nature

    of

    the

    Early Royal

    Society,"

    Historical Journal

    12

    (1969), 217-239.

    Thi t t d l d d f 146 155 94 33 W d 13 A 2014 23 34 08 UTC

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp